Set (mathematics)
In mathematics, a set is a collection of distinct objects, considered as an object in its own right. For example, the numbers 2, 4, and 6 are distinct objects when considered separately, but when they are considered collectively they form a single set of size three, written {2, 4, 6}. The concept of a set is one of the most fundamental in mathematics. Developed at the end of the 19th century, set theory is now a ubiquitous part of mathematics, and can be used as a foundation from which nearly all of mathematics can be derived. In mathematics education, elementary topics from set theory such as Venn diagrams are taught at a young age, while more advanced concepts are taught as part of a university degree.
The German word Menge, rendered as "set" in English, was coined by Bernard Bolzano in his work The Paradoxes of the Infinite.
Contents
1 Definition
2 Describing sets
3 Membership
3.1 Subsets
3.2 Power sets
4 Cardinality
5 Special sets
6 Basic operations
6.1 Unions
6.2 Intersections
6.3 Complements
6.4 Cartesian product
7 Applications
8 Axiomatic set theory
9 Principle of inclusion and exclusion
10 De Morgan's laws
11 See also
12 Notes
13 References
Definition
A set is a well-defined collection of distinct objects. The objects that make up a set (also known as the set's elements or members) can be anything: numbers, people, letters of the alphabet, other sets, and so on. Georg Cantor, one of the founders of set theory, gave the following definition of a set at the beginning of his Beiträge zur Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre:[1]
.mw-parser-output .templatequote{overflow:hidden;margin:1em 0;padding:0 40px}.mw-parser-output .templatequote .templatequotecite{line-height:1.5em;text-align:left;padding-left:1.6em;margin-top:0}
A set is a gathering together into a whole of definite, distinct objects of our perception [Anschauung] or of our thought—which are called elements of the set.
Sets are conventionally denoted with capital letters. Sets A and B are equal if and only if they have precisely the same elements.[2]
For technical reasons, Cantor's definition turned out to be inadequate; today, in contexts where more rigor is required, one can use axiomatic set theory, in which the notion of a "set" is taken as a primitive notion and the properties of sets are defined by a collection of axioms. The most basic properties are that a set can have elements, and that two sets are equal (one and the same) if and only if every element of each set is an element of the other; this property is called the extensionality of sets.
Describing sets
There are two ways of describing, or specifying the members of, a set. One way is by intensional definition, using a rule or semantic description:
A is the set whose members are the first four positive integers.
B is the set of colors of the French flag.
The second way is by extension – that is, listing each member of the set. An extensional definition is denoted by enclosing the list of members in curly brackets:
C = {4, 2, 1, 3}
D = {blue, white, red}.
One often has the choice of specifying a set either intensionally or extensionally. In the examples above, for instance, A = C and B = D.
In an extensional definition, a set member can be listed two or more times, for example, {11, 6, 6}. However, per extensionality, two definitions of sets which differ only in that one of the definitions lists members multiple times define the same set. Hence, the set {11, 6, 6} is identical to the set {11, 6}. Moreover, the order in which the elements of a set are listed is irrelevant (unlike for a sequence or tuple), so {6, 11} is yet again the same set.
For sets with many elements, the enumeration of members can be abbreviated. For instance, the set of the first thousand positive integers may be specified extensionally as
- {1, 2, 3, ..., 1000},
where the ellipsis ("...") indicates that the list continues in the obvious way.
The notation with braces may also be used in an intensional specification of a set. In this usage, the braces have the meaning "the set of all ...". So, E = {playing card suits} is the set whose four members are spades, diamonds, hearts, and clubs. A more general form of this is set-builder notation, through which, for instance, the set F of the twenty smallest integers that are four less than a perfect square can be denoted
- F={n2−4:n is an integer, and 0≤n≤19}.{displaystyle F={n^{2}-4:n{text{ is an integer, and }}0leq nleq 19}.}
In this notation, the colon (":") means "such that", and the description can be interpreted as "F is the set of all numbers of the form n2 − 4, such that n is a whole number in the range from 0 to 19 inclusive." Sometimes the vertical bar ("|") is used instead of the colon.
Membership
If B is a set and x is one of the objects of B, this is denoted as x ∈ B, and is read as "x is an element of B", as "x belongs to B", or short "x is in B". If y is not a member of B then this is written as y ∉ B, read as "y is not an element of B", or as analogous negated forms.
For example, with respect to the sets A = {1, 2, 3, 4}, B = {blue, white, red}, and F = {n2 − 4 : n is an integer, and 0 ≤ n ≤ 19} defined above,
- 4 ∈ A and 12 ∈ F; and
- 9 ∉ F and green ∉ B.
Subsets
If every element of set A is also in B, then A is said to be a subset of B, written A ⊆ B (pronounced A is contained in B). Equivalently, one can write B ⊇ A, read as B is a superset of A, B includes A, or B contains A. The relationship between sets established by ⊆ is called inclusion or containment, and is given also for equal sets, that is, equality of sets is the same as mutual containment in each other: A ⊆ B and B ⊆ A is equivalent to A = B.
If A is a subset of, but not equal to, B, then A is called a proper subset of B, written A ⊊ B, or simply A ⊂ B (A is a proper subset of B), or B ⊋ A (B is a proper superset of A, B ⊃ A).
The expressions A ⊂ B and B ⊃ A are used differently by different authors; some authors use them to mean the same as A ⊆ B (respectively B ⊇ A), whereas others use them to mean the same as A ⊊ B (respectively B ⊋ A).
Examples:
- The set of all men is a proper subset of the set of all people.
- {1, 3} ⊆ {1, 2, 3, 4}.
- {1, 2, 3, 4} ⊆ {1, 2, 3, 4}.
The empty set is a subset of every set, and every set is a subset of itself:
- ∅ ⊆ A.
A ⊆ A.
The above characterization of set equality can be used to show that two sets described differently are, in fact, equal:
A = B if and only if A ⊆ B and B ⊆ A.
A partition of a set S is a set of nonempty subsets of S such that every element x in S is in exactly one of these subsets, that is, any two sets of the partition contain no element in common, they are said to be disjoint, and the union of all elements of the partition that are sets themselves, make up S.
Power sets
The power set of a set S is the set of all subsets of S. The power set contains S itself and the empty set because these are both subsets of S. For example, the power set of the set {1, 2, 3} is {{1, 2, 3}, {1, 2}, {1, 3}, {2, 3}, {1}, {2}, {3}, ∅}. The power set of a set S is usually written as P(S).
The power set of a finite set with n elements has 2n elements. For example, the set {1, 2, 3} contains three elements, and the power set shown above contains 23 = 8 elements.
The power set of an infinite (either countable or uncountable) set is always uncountable. Moreover, the power set of a set is always strictly "bigger" than the original set in the sense that there is no way to pair every element of S with exactly one element of P(S). (There is never an onto map or surjection from S onto P(S).)
Every partition of a set S is a subset of the powerset of S.
Cardinality
The cardinality of a set S, denoted |S|, is the number of members of S. For example, if B = {blue, white, red}, then |B| = 3.
There is a unique set with no members, called the empty set (or the null set), which is denoted by the symbol ∅ (other notations are used; see empty set). The cardinality of the empty set is zero. For example, the set of all three-sided squares has zero members and thus is the empty set. Though it may seem trivial, the empty set, like the number zero, is important in mathematics. Indeed, the existence of this set is one of the fundamental concepts of axiomatic set theory.
Some sets have infinite cardinality. The set N of natural numbers, for instance, is infinite. Some infinite cardinalities are greater than others. For instance, the set of real numbers has greater cardinality than the set of natural numbers. However, it can be shown that the cardinality of (which is to say, the number of points on) a straight line is the same as the cardinality of any segment of that line, of the entire plane, and indeed of any finite-dimensional Euclidean space.
Special sets
There are some sets or kinds of sets that hold great mathematical importance and are referred to with such regularity that they have acquired special names and notational conventions to identify them. One of these is the empty set, denoted { } or ∅. A set with exactly one element, x, is a unit set, or singleton, {x}.[2]
Many of these sets are represented using blackboard bold or bold typeface. Special sets of numbers include
P or ℙ, denoting the set of all primes: P = {2, 3, 5, 7, 11, 13, 17, ...}.
N or N{displaystyle mathbb {N} }, denoting the set of all natural numbers: N = {0, 1, 2, 3, ...} (sometimes defined excluding 0).
Z or Z{displaystyle mathbb {Z} }, denoting the set of all integers (whether positive, negative or zero): Z = {..., −2, −1, 0, 1, 2, ...}.
Q or ℚ, denoting the set of all rational numbers (that is, the set of all proper and improper fractions): Q = {a/b | a, b ∈ Z, b ≠ 0}. For example, 1/4 ∈ Q and 11/6 ∈ Q. All integers are in this set since every integer a can be expressed as the fraction a/1 (Z ⊊ Q).
R or R{displaystyle mathbb {R} }, denoting the set of all real numbers. This set includes all rational numbers, together with all irrational numbers (that is, algebraic numbers that cannot be rewritten as fractions such as √2, as well as transcendental numbers such as π, e).
C or ℂ, denoting the set of all complex numbers: C = {a + bi|a, b ∈ R}. For example, 1 + 2i ∈ C.
H or ℍ, denoting the set of all quaternions: H = {a + bi + cj + dk|a, b, c, d ∈ R}. For example, 1 + i + 2j − k ∈ H.
Each of the above sets of numbers has an infinite number of elements, and each can be considered to be a proper subset of the sets listed below it. The primes are used less frequently than the others outside of number theory and related fields.
Positive and negative sets are sometimes denoted by superscript plus and minus signs, respectively. For example, ℚ+ represents the set of positive rational numbers.
Basic operations
There are several fundamental operations for constructing new sets from given sets.
Unions
Two sets can be "added" together. The union of A and B, denoted by A ∪ B, is the set of all things that are members of either A or B.
Examples:
- {1, 2} ∪ {1, 2} = {1, 2}.
- {1, 2} ∪ {2, 3} = {1, 2, 3}.
- {1, 2, 3} ∪ {3, 4, 5} = {1, 2, 3, 4, 5}
Some basic properties of unions:
- A ∪ B = B ∪ A.
- A ∪ (B ∪ C) = (A ∪ B) ∪ C.
- A ⊆ (A ∪ B).
- A ∪ A = A.
- A ∪ U = U.
- A ∪ ∅ = A.
A ⊆ B if and only if A ∪ B = B.
Intersections
A new set can also be constructed by determining which members two sets have "in common". The intersection of A and B, denoted by A ∩ B, is the set of all things that are members of both A and B. If A ∩ B = ∅, then A and B are said to be disjoint.
Examples:
- {1, 2} ∩ {1, 2} = {1, 2}.
- {1, 2} ∩ {2, 3} = {2}.
Some basic properties of intersections:
- A ∩ B = B ∩ A.
- A ∩ (B ∩ C) = (A ∩ B) ∩ C.
- A ∩ B ⊆ A.
- A ∩ A = A.
- A ∩ U = A.
- A ∩ ∅ = ∅.
A ⊆ B if and only if A ∩ B = A.
Complements
Two sets can also be "subtracted". The relative complement of B in A (also called the set-theoretic difference of A and B), denoted by A B (or A − B), is the set of all elements that are members of A but not members of B. Note that it is valid to "subtract" members of a set that are not in the set, such as removing the element green from the set {1, 2, 3}; doing so has no effect.
In certain settings all sets under discussion are considered to be subsets of a given universal set U. In such cases, U A is called the absolute complement or simply complement of A, and is denoted by A′.
- A′ = U A
Examples:
- {1, 2} {1, 2} = ∅.
- {1, 2, 3, 4} {1, 3} = {2, 4}.
- If U is the set of integers, E is the set of even integers, and O is the set of odd integers, then U E = E′ = O.
Some basic properties of complements:
A B ≠ B A for A ≠ B.- A ∪ A′ = U.
- A ∩ A′ = ∅.
- (A′)′ = A.
- ∅ A = ∅.
- A ∅ = A.
- A A = ∅.
- A U = ∅.
A A′ = A and A′ A = A′.
U′ = ∅ and ∅′ = U.
A B = A ∩ B′.- if A ⊆ B then A B = ∅.
An extension of the complement is the symmetric difference, defined for sets A, B as
- AΔB=(A∖B)∪(B∖A).{displaystyle A,Delta ,B=(Asetminus B)cup (Bsetminus A).}
For example, the symmetric difference of {7, 8, 9, 10} and {9, 10, 11, 12} is the set {7, 8, 11, 12}. The power set of any set becomes a Boolean ring with symmetric difference as the addition of the ring (with the empty set as neutral element) and intersection as the multiplication of the ring.
Cartesian product
A new set can be constructed by associating every element of one set with every element of another set. The Cartesian product of two sets A and B, denoted by A × B is the set of all ordered pairs (a, b) such that a is a member of A and b is a member of B.
Examples:
- {1, 2} × {red, white, green} = {(1, red), (1, white), (1, green), (2, red), (2, white), (2, green)}.
- {1, 2} × {1, 2} = {(1, 1), (1, 2), (2, 1), (2, 2)}.
- {a, b, c} × {d, e, f} = {(a, d), (a, e), (a, f), (b, d), (b, e), (b, f), (c, d), (c, e), (c, f)}.
Some basic properties of Cartesian products:
- A × ∅ = ∅.
- A × (B ∪ C) = (A × B) ∪ (A × C).
- (A ∪ B) × C = (A × C) ∪ (B × C).
Let A and B be finite sets; then the cardinality of the Cartesian product is the product of the cardinalities:
- | A × B | = | B × A | = | A | × | B |.
Applications
Set theory is seen as the foundation from which virtually all of mathematics can be derived. For example, structures in abstract algebra, such as groups, fields and rings, are sets closed under one or more operations.
One of the main applications of naive set theory is constructing relations. A relation from a domain A to a codomain B is a subset of the Cartesian product A × B. Given this concept, we are quick to see that the set F of all ordered pairs (x, x2), where x is real, is quite familiar. It has a domain set R and a codomain set that is also R, because the set of all squares is subset of the set of all real numbers. If placed in functional notation, this relation becomes f(x) = x2. The reason these two are equivalent is for any given value, y that the function is defined for, its corresponding ordered pair, (y, y2) is a member of the set F.
Axiomatic set theory
Although initially naive set theory, which defines a set merely as any well-defined collection, was well accepted, it soon ran into several obstacles. It was found that this definition spawned several paradoxes, most notably:
Russell's paradox – It shows that the "set of all sets that do not contain themselves," i.e. the "set" {x|x is a set and x ∉ x} does not exist.
Cantor's paradox – It shows that "the set of all sets" cannot exist.
The reason is that the phrase well-defined is not very well-defined. It was important to free set theory of these paradoxes because nearly all of mathematics was being redefined in terms of set theory. In an attempt to avoid these paradoxes, set theory was axiomatized based on first-order logic, and thus axiomatic set theory was born.
For most purposes, however, naive set theory is still useful.
Principle of inclusion and exclusion
The inclusion–exclusion principle is a counting technique that can be used to count the number of elements in a union of two sets, if the size of each set and the size of their intersection are known. It can be expressed symbolically as
- |A∪B|=|A|+|B|−|A∩B|.{displaystyle |Acup B|=|A|+|B|-|Acap B|.}
A more general form of the principle can be used to find the cardinality of any finite union of sets:
- |A1∪A2∪A3∪…∪An|=(|A1|+|A2|+|A3|+…|An|)−(|A1∩A2|+|A1∩A3|+…|An−1∩An|)+…+(−1)n−1(|A1∩A2∩A3∩…∩An|).{displaystyle {begin{aligned}left|A_{1}cup A_{2}cup A_{3}cup ldots cup A_{n}right|=&left(left|A_{1}right|+left|A_{2}right|+left|A_{3}right|+ldots left|A_{n}right|right)\&{}-left(left|A_{1}cap A_{2}right|+left|A_{1}cap A_{3}right|+ldots left|A_{n-1}cap A_{n}right|right)\&{}+ldots \&{}+left(-1right)^{n-1}left(left|A_{1}cap A_{2}cap A_{3}cap ldots cap A_{n}right|right).end{aligned}}}
De Morgan's laws
Augustus De Morgan stated two laws about sets.
If A and B are any two sets then,
- (A ∪ B)′ = A′ ∩ B′
The complement of A union B equals the complement of A intersected with the complement of B.
- (A ∩ B)′ = A′ ∪ B′
The complement of A intersected with B is equal to the complement of A union to the complement of B.
See also
- Set notation
- Mathematical object
- Alternative set theory
- Axiomatic set theory
- Category of sets
- Class (set theory)
- Dense set
- Family of sets
- Fuzzy set
- Internal set
- Mereology
- Multiset
- Naive set theory
- Principia Mathematica
- Rough set
- Russell's paradox
- Sequence (mathematics)
- Taxonomy
- Tuple
Notes
^ "Eine Menge, ist die Zusammenfassung bestimmter, wohlunterschiedener Objekte unserer Anschauung oder unseres Denkens – welche Elemente der Menge genannt werden – zu einem Ganzen." "Archived copy". Archived from the original on 2011-06-10. Retrieved 2011-04-22.CS1 maint: Archived copy as title (link).mw-parser-output cite.citation{font-style:inherit}.mw-parser-output .citation q{quotes:"""""""'""'"}.mw-parser-output .citation .cs1-lock-free a{background:url("//upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/6/65/Lock-green.svg/9px-Lock-green.svg.png")no-repeat;background-position:right .1em center}.mw-parser-output .citation .cs1-lock-limited a,.mw-parser-output .citation .cs1-lock-registration a{background:url("//upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/d/d6/Lock-gray-alt-2.svg/9px-Lock-gray-alt-2.svg.png")no-repeat;background-position:right .1em center}.mw-parser-output .citation .cs1-lock-subscription a{background:url("//upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/a/aa/Lock-red-alt-2.svg/9px-Lock-red-alt-2.svg.png")no-repeat;background-position:right .1em center}.mw-parser-output .cs1-subscription,.mw-parser-output .cs1-registration{color:#555}.mw-parser-output .cs1-subscription span,.mw-parser-output .cs1-registration span{border-bottom:1px dotted;cursor:help}.mw-parser-output .cs1-ws-icon a{background:url("//upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/4/4c/Wikisource-logo.svg/12px-Wikisource-logo.svg.png")no-repeat;background-position:right .1em center}.mw-parser-output code.cs1-code{color:inherit;background:inherit;border:inherit;padding:inherit}.mw-parser-output .cs1-hidden-error{display:none;font-size:100%}.mw-parser-output .cs1-visible-error{font-size:100%}.mw-parser-output .cs1-maint{display:none;color:#33aa33;margin-left:0.3em}.mw-parser-output .cs1-subscription,.mw-parser-output .cs1-registration,.mw-parser-output .cs1-format{font-size:95%}.mw-parser-output .cs1-kern-left,.mw-parser-output .cs1-kern-wl-left{padding-left:0.2em}.mw-parser-output .cs1-kern-right,.mw-parser-output .cs1-kern-wl-right{padding-right:0.2em}
^ ab
Stoll, Robert. Sets, Logic and Axiomatic Theories. W. H. Freeman and Company. p. 5.
References
Dauben, Joseph W., Georg Cantor: His Mathematics and Philosophy of the Infinite, Boston: Harvard University Press (1979)
ISBN 978-0-691-02447-9.
Halmos, Paul R., Naive Set Theory, Princeton, N.J.: Van Nostrand (1960)
ISBN 0-387-90092-6.- Stoll, Robert R., Set Theory and Logic, Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Publications (1979)
ISBN 0-486-63829-4. - Velleman, Daniel, How To Prove It: A Structured Approach, Cambridge University Press (2006)
ISBN 978-0-521-67599-4
Comments
Post a Comment