Uncountable set





In mathematics, an uncountable set (or uncountably infinite set)[1] is an infinite set that contains too many elements to be countable. The uncountability of a set is closely related to its cardinal number: a set is uncountable if its cardinal number is larger than that of the set of all natural numbers.




Contents






  • 1 Characterizations


  • 2 Properties


  • 3 Examples


  • 4 Without the axiom of choice


  • 5 See also


  • 6 References


  • 7 External links





Characterizations


There are many equivalent characterizations of uncountability. A set X is uncountable if and only if any of the following conditions hold:



  • There is no injective function from X to the set of natural numbers.


  • X is nonempty and for every ω-sequence of elements of X, there exist at least one element of X not included in it. That is, X is nonempty and there is no surjective function from the natural numbers to X.

  • The cardinality of X is neither finite nor equal to 0{displaystyle aleph _{0}}aleph _{0} (aleph-null, the cardinality of the natural numbers).

  • The set X has cardinality strictly greater than 0{displaystyle aleph _{0}}aleph _{0}.


The first three of these characterizations can be proven equivalent in Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice, but the equivalence of the third and fourth cannot be proved without additional choice principles.



Properties


  • If an uncountable set X is a subset of set Y, then Y is uncountable.


Examples


The best known example of an uncountable set is the set R of all real numbers; Cantor's diagonal argument shows that this set is uncountable. The diagonalization proof technique can also be used to show that several other sets are uncountable, such as the set of all infinite sequences of natural numbers and the set of all subsets of the set of natural numbers. The cardinality of R is often called the cardinality of the continuum and denoted by c, or 2ℵ0{displaystyle 2^{aleph _{0}}}2^{aleph _{0}}, or 1{displaystyle beth _{1}}beth _{1} (beth-one).


The Cantor set is an uncountable subset of R. The Cantor set is a fractal and has Hausdorff dimension greater than zero but less than one (R has dimension one). This is an example of the following fact: any subset of R of Hausdorff dimension strictly greater than zero must be uncountable.


Another example of an uncountable set is the set of all functions from R to R. This set is even "more uncountable" than R in the sense that the cardinality of this set is 2{displaystyle beth _{2}}beth _{2} (beth-two), which is larger than 1{displaystyle beth _{1}}beth _{1}.


A more abstract example of an uncountable set is the set of all countable ordinal numbers, denoted by Ω or ω1. The cardinality of Ω is denoted 1{displaystyle aleph _{1}}aleph _{1} (aleph-one). It can be shown, using the axiom of choice, that 1{displaystyle aleph _{1}}aleph _{1} is the smallest uncountable cardinal number. Thus either 1{displaystyle beth _{1}}beth _{1}, the cardinality of the reals, is equal to 1{displaystyle aleph _{1}}aleph _{1} or it is strictly larger. Georg Cantor was the first to propose the question of whether 1{displaystyle beth _{1}}beth _{1} is equal to 1{displaystyle aleph _{1}}aleph _{1}. In 1900, David Hilbert posed this question as the first of his 23 problems. The statement that 1=ℶ1{displaystyle aleph _{1}=beth _{1}}aleph _{1}=beth _{1} is now called the continuum hypothesis and is known to be independent of the Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms for set theory (including the axiom of choice).



Without the axiom of choice



Without the axiom of choice, there might exist cardinalities incomparable to 0{displaystyle aleph _{0}}aleph _{0} (namely, the cardinalities of Dedekind-finite infinite sets). Sets of these cardinalities satisfy the first three characterizations above but not the fourth characterization. Because these sets are not larger than the natural numbers in the sense of cardinality, some may not want to call them uncountable.


If the axiom of choice holds, the following conditions on a cardinal κ{displaystyle kappa }kappa are equivalent:



  • κ0;{displaystyle kappa nleq aleph _{0};}kappa nleq aleph _{0};


  • κ>ℵ0;{displaystyle kappa >aleph _{0};}kappa >aleph _{0}; and


  • κ1{displaystyle kappa geq aleph _{1}}kappa geq aleph _{1}, where 1=|ω1|{displaystyle aleph _{1}=|omega _{1}|}aleph _{1}=|omega _{1}| and ω1{displaystyle omega _{1}}omega _{1} is least initial ordinal greater than ω.{displaystyle omega .}omega .


However, these may all be different if the axiom of choice fails. So it is not obvious which one is the appropriate generalization of "uncountability" when the axiom fails. It may be best to avoid using the word in this case and specify which of these one means.



See also



  • Aleph number

  • Beth number

  • Injective function

  • Natural number



References





  1. ^ Uncountably Infinite — from Wolfram MathWorld





  • Halmos, Paul, Naive Set Theory. Princeton, NJ: D. Van Nostrand Company, 1960. Reprinted by Springer-Verlag, New York, 1974. .mw-parser-output cite.citation{font-style:inherit}.mw-parser-output q{quotes:"""""""'""'"}.mw-parser-output code.cs1-code{color:inherit;background:inherit;border:inherit;padding:inherit}.mw-parser-output .cs1-lock-free a{background:url("//upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/6/65/Lock-green.svg/9px-Lock-green.svg.png")no-repeat;background-position:right .1em center}.mw-parser-output .cs1-lock-limited a,.mw-parser-output .cs1-lock-registration a{background:url("//upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/d/d6/Lock-gray-alt-2.svg/9px-Lock-gray-alt-2.svg.png")no-repeat;background-position:right .1em center}.mw-parser-output .cs1-lock-subscription a{background:url("//upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/a/aa/Lock-red-alt-2.svg/9px-Lock-red-alt-2.svg.png")no-repeat;background-position:right .1em center}.mw-parser-output .cs1-subscription,.mw-parser-output .cs1-registration{color:#555}.mw-parser-output .cs1-subscription span,.mw-parser-output .cs1-registration span{border-bottom:1px dotted;cursor:help}.mw-parser-output .cs1-hidden-error{display:none;font-size:100%}.mw-parser-output .cs1-visible-error{font-size:100%}.mw-parser-output .cs1-subscription,.mw-parser-output .cs1-registration,.mw-parser-output .cs1-format{font-size:95%}.mw-parser-output .cs1-kern-left,.mw-parser-output .cs1-kern-wl-left{padding-left:0.2em}.mw-parser-output .cs1-kern-right,.mw-parser-output .cs1-kern-wl-right{padding-right:0.2em}
    ISBN 0-387-90092-6 (Springer-Verlag edition). Reprinted by Martino Fine Books, 2011.
    ISBN 978-1-61427-131-4 (Paperback edition).


  • Jech, Thomas (2002), Set Theory, Springer Monographs in Mathematics (3rd millennium ed.), Springer, ISBN 3-540-44085-2



External links


  • Proof that R is uncountable









Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Information security

章鱼与海女图

Farm Security Administration