Aleph number




infinite cardinal number




Aleph-naught, or aleph-null, the smallest infinite cardinal number


In mathematics, and in particular set theory, the aleph numbers are a sequence of numbers used to represent the cardinality (or size) of infinite sets that can be well-ordered. They are named after the symbol used to denote them, the Hebrew letter aleph ({displaystyle aleph }aleph ) (though in older mathematics books the letter aleph is often printed upside down by accident,[1] partly because a Monotype matrix for aleph was mistakenly constructed the wrong way up).[2]


The cardinality of the natural numbers is 0{displaystyle aleph _{0}}aleph _{0} (read aleph-naught or aleph-zero; the German term aleph-null is also sometimes used), the next larger cardinality is aleph-one 1{displaystyle aleph _{1}}aleph _{1}, then 2{displaystyle aleph _{2}}aleph _{2} and so on. Continuing in this manner, it is possible to define a cardinal number α{displaystyle aleph _{alpha }}aleph _{alpha } for every ordinal number α, as described below.


The concept and notation are due to Georg Cantor,[3] who defined the notion of cardinality and realized that infinite sets can have different cardinalities.


The aleph numbers differ from the infinity (∞) commonly found in algebra and calculus. Alephs measure the sizes of sets; infinity, on the other hand, is commonly defined as an extreme limit of the real number line (applied to a function or sequence that "diverges to infinity" or "increases without bound"), or an extreme point of the extended real number line.




Contents






  • 1 Aleph-naught


  • 2 Aleph-one


  • 3 Continuum hypothesis


  • 4 Aleph-ω


  • 5 Aleph-α for general α


  • 6 Fixed points of omega


  • 7 Role of axiom of choice


  • 8 See also


  • 9 Notes


  • 10 References


  • 11 External links





Aleph-naught


0{displaystyle aleph _{0}}aleph _{0} (aleph-naught, also aleph-zero or the German term Aleph-null) is the cardinality of the set of all natural numbers, and is an infinite cardinal. The set of all finite ordinals, called ω or ω0 (where ω is the lowercase Greek letter omega), has cardinality 0{displaystyle aleph _{0}}aleph _{0}. A set has cardinality 0{displaystyle aleph _{0}}aleph _{0} if and only if it is countably infinite, that is, there is a bijection (one-to-one correspondence) between it and the natural numbers. Examples of such sets are



  • the set of all square numbers, the set of all cubic numbers, the set of all fourth powers, ...

  • the set of all perfect powers, the set of all prime powers,

  • the set of all even numbers, the set of all odd numbers,

  • the set of all prime numbers, the set of all composite numbers,

  • the set of all integers,

  • the set of all rational numbers,

  • the set of all constructible numbers (in the geometric sense),

  • the set of all algebraic numbers,

  • the set of all computable numbers,

  • the set of all definable numbers,

  • the set of all binary strings of finite length, and

  • the set of all finite subsets of any given countably infinite set.


These infinite ordinals: ω, ω+1, ω·2, ω2, ωω and ε0 are among the countably infinite sets.[4] For example, the sequence (with ordinality ω·2) of all positive odd integers followed by all positive even integers


{1, 3, 5, 7, 9, ..., 2, 4, 6, 8, 10, ...}

is an ordering of the set (with cardinality 0{displaystyle aleph _{0}}aleph _{0}) of positive integers.


If the axiom of countable choice (a weaker version of the axiom of choice) holds, then 0{displaystyle aleph _{0}}aleph _{0} is smaller than any other infinite cardinal.



Aleph-one


1{displaystyle aleph _{1}}aleph _{1} is the cardinality of the set of all countable ordinal numbers, called ω1 or sometimes Ω. This ω1 is itself an ordinal number larger than all countable ones, so it is an uncountable set. Therefore, 1{displaystyle aleph _{1}}aleph _{1} is distinct from 0{displaystyle aleph _{0}}aleph _{0}. The definition of 1{displaystyle aleph _{1}}aleph _{1} implies (in ZF, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice) that no cardinal number is between 0{displaystyle aleph _{0}}aleph _{0} and 1{displaystyle aleph _{1}}aleph _{1}. If the axiom of choice is used, it can be further proved that the class of cardinal numbers is totally ordered, and thus 1{displaystyle aleph _{1}}aleph _{1} is the second-smallest infinite cardinal number. Using the axiom of choice we can show one of the most useful properties of the set ω1: any countable subset of ω1 has an upper bound in ω1. (This follows from the fact that the union of a countable number of countable sets is itself countable, one of the most common applications of the axiom of choice.) This fact is analogous to the situation in 0{displaystyle aleph _{0}}aleph _{0}: every finite set of natural numbers has a maximum which is also a natural number, and finite unions of finite sets are finite.


ω1 is actually a useful concept, if somewhat exotic-sounding. An example application is "closing" with respect to countable operations; e.g., trying to explicitly describe the σ-algebra generated by an arbitrary collection of subsets (see e. g. Borel hierarchy). This is harder than most explicit descriptions of "generation" in algebra (vector spaces, groups, etc.) because in those cases we only have to close with respect to finite operations—sums, products, and the like. The process involves defining, for each countable ordinal, via transfinite induction, a set by "throwing in" all possible countable unions and complements, and taking the union of all that over all of ω1.


Every uncountable coanalytic subset of a Polish space X{displaystyle X}X has
cardinality 1{displaystyle aleph _{1}}aleph _{1} or 2ℵ0{displaystyle 2^{aleph _{0}}}2^{aleph _{0}}.[citation needed]



Continuum hypothesis




The cardinality of the set of real numbers (cardinality of the continuum) is 2ℵ0{displaystyle 2^{aleph _{0}}}2^{aleph _{0}}. It cannot be determined from ZFC (Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice) where this number fits exactly in the aleph number hierarchy, but it follows from ZFC that the continuum hypothesis, CH, is equivalent to the identity



2ℵ0=ℵ1{displaystyle 2^{aleph _{0}}=aleph _{1}}2^{{aleph _{0}}}=aleph _{1} [5]

The CH states that there is no set whose cardinality is strictly between that of the integers and the real numbers. CH is independent of ZFC: it can be neither proven nor disproven within the context of that axiom system (provided that ZFC is consistent). That CH is consistent with ZFC was demonstrated by Kurt Gödel in 1940 when he showed that its negation is not a theorem of ZFC. That it is independent of ZFC was demonstrated by Paul Cohen in 1963 when he showed, conversely, that the CH itself is not a theorem of ZFC by the (then novel) method of forcing. [6]



Aleph-ω


Conventionally the smallest infinite ordinal is denoted ω, and the cardinal number ω{displaystyle aleph _{omega }}aleph _{omega } is the least upper bound of


{ℵn:n∈{0,1,2,…}}{displaystyle left{,aleph _{n}:nin left{,0,1,2,dots ,right},right}}left{,aleph _{n}:nin left{,0,1,2,dots ,right},right}

among alephs.


Aleph-ω is the first uncountable cardinal number that can be demonstrated within Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory not to be equal to the cardinality of the set of all real numbers; for any positive integer n we can consistently assume that 2ℵ0=ℵn{displaystyle 2^{aleph _{0}}=aleph _{n}}2^{aleph _{0}}=aleph _{n}, and moreover it is possible to assume 2ℵ0{displaystyle 2^{aleph _{0}}}2^{aleph _{0}} is as large as we like. We are only forced to avoid setting it to certain special cardinals with cofinality 0{displaystyle aleph _{0}}aleph _{0}, meaning there is an unbounded function from 0{displaystyle aleph _{0}}aleph _{0} to it (see Easton's theorem).



Aleph-α for general α


To define α{displaystyle aleph _{alpha }}aleph _{alpha } for arbitrary ordinal number α{displaystyle alpha }alpha , we must define the successor cardinal operation, which assigns to any cardinal number ρ the next larger well-ordered cardinal ρ+ (if the axiom of choice holds, this is the next larger cardinal).


We can then define the aleph numbers as follows:


0=ω{displaystyle aleph _{0}=omega }aleph _{0}=omega

α+1=ℵα+{displaystyle aleph _{alpha +1}=aleph _{alpha }^{+}}aleph _{alpha +1}=aleph _{alpha }^{+}

and for λ, an infinite limit ordinal,


λ=⋃ββ.{displaystyle aleph _{lambda }=bigcup _{beta <lambda }aleph _{beta }.}aleph _{lambda }=bigcup _{beta <lambda }aleph _{beta }.

The α-th infinite initial ordinal is written ωα{displaystyle omega _{alpha }}omega _{alpha }. Its cardinality is written α{displaystyle aleph _{alpha }}aleph _{alpha }.
In ZFC, the aleph function {displaystyle aleph }aleph is a bijection from the ordinals to the infinite cardinals.[7]



Fixed points of omega


For any ordinal α we have


αωα.{displaystyle alpha leq omega _{alpha }.}alpha leq omega _{alpha }.

In many cases ωα{displaystyle omega _{alpha }}omega _{alpha } is strictly greater than α. For example, for any successor ordinal α this holds. There are, however, some limit ordinals which are fixed points of the omega function, because of the fixed-point lemma for normal functions. The first such is the limit of the sequence


ω, ωω, ωωω, ….{displaystyle omega , omega _{omega }, omega _{omega _{omega }}, ldots .}omega , omega _{omega }, omega _{omega _{omega }}, ldots .

Any weakly inaccessible cardinal is also a fixed point of the aleph function.[8] This can be shown in ZFC as follows. Suppose κ=ℵλ{displaystyle kappa =aleph _{lambda }}kappa =aleph _{lambda } is a weakly inaccessible cardinal. If λ{displaystyle lambda }lambda were a successor ordinal, then λ{displaystyle aleph _{lambda }}aleph _{lambda } would be a successor cardinal and hence not weakly inaccessible. If λ{displaystyle lambda }lambda were a limit ordinal less than κ{displaystyle kappa }kappa , then its cofinality (and thus the cofinality of λ{displaystyle aleph _{lambda }}aleph _{lambda }) would be less than κ{displaystyle kappa }kappa and so κ{displaystyle kappa }kappa would not be regular and thus not weakly inaccessible. Thus λκ{displaystyle lambda geq kappa }lambda geq kappa and consequently λ{displaystyle lambda =kappa }lambda =kappa which makes it a fixed point.



Role of axiom of choice


The cardinality of any infinite ordinal number is an aleph number. Every aleph is the cardinality of some ordinal. The least of these is its initial ordinal. Any set whose cardinality is an aleph is equinumerous with an ordinal and is thus well-orderable.


Each finite set is well-orderable, but does not have an aleph as its cardinality.


The assumption that the cardinality of each infinite set is an aleph number is equivalent over ZF to the existence of a well-ordering of every set, which in turn is equivalent to the axiom of choice. ZFC set theory, which includes the axiom of choice, implies that every infinite set has an aleph number as its cardinality (i.e. is equinumerous with its initial ordinal), and thus the initial ordinals of the aleph numbers serve as a class of representatives for all possible infinite cardinal numbers.


When cardinality is studied in ZF without the axiom of choice, it is no longer possible to prove that each infinite set has some aleph number as its cardinality; the sets whose cardinality is an aleph number are exactly the infinite sets that can be well-ordered. The method of Scott's trick is sometimes used as an alternative way to construct representatives for cardinal numbers in the setting of ZF. For example, one can define card(S) to be the set of sets with the same cardinality as S of minimum possible rank. This has the property that card(S) = card(T) if and only if S and T have the same cardinality. (The set card(S) does not have the same cardinality of S in general, but all its elements do.)



See also



  • Regular cardinal

  • Ordinal number



Notes





  1. ^ For example, in (Sierpiński 1958, p.402) the letter aleph appears both the right way up and upside down


  2. ^ Swanson, Ellen; O'Sean, Arlene Ann; Schleyer, Antoinette Tingley (1999) [1979], Mathematics into type: Copy editing and proofreading of mathematics for editorial assistants and authors (updated ed.), Providence, R.I.: American Mathematical Society, p. 16, ISBN 0-8218-0053-1, MR 0553111.mw-parser-output cite.citation{font-style:inherit}.mw-parser-output q{quotes:"""""""'""'"}.mw-parser-output code.cs1-code{color:inherit;background:inherit;border:inherit;padding:inherit}.mw-parser-output .cs1-lock-free a{background:url("//upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/6/65/Lock-green.svg/9px-Lock-green.svg.png")no-repeat;background-position:right .1em center}.mw-parser-output .cs1-lock-limited a,.mw-parser-output .cs1-lock-registration a{background:url("//upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/d/d6/Lock-gray-alt-2.svg/9px-Lock-gray-alt-2.svg.png")no-repeat;background-position:right .1em center}.mw-parser-output .cs1-lock-subscription a{background:url("//upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/a/aa/Lock-red-alt-2.svg/9px-Lock-red-alt-2.svg.png")no-repeat;background-position:right .1em center}.mw-parser-output .cs1-subscription,.mw-parser-output .cs1-registration{color:#555}.mw-parser-output .cs1-subscription span,.mw-parser-output .cs1-registration span{border-bottom:1px dotted;cursor:help}.mw-parser-output .cs1-hidden-error{display:none;font-size:100%}.mw-parser-output .cs1-visible-error{font-size:100%}.mw-parser-output .cs1-subscription,.mw-parser-output .cs1-registration,.mw-parser-output .cs1-format{font-size:95%}.mw-parser-output .cs1-kern-left,.mw-parser-output .cs1-kern-wl-left{padding-left:0.2em}.mw-parser-output .cs1-kern-right,.mw-parser-output .cs1-kern-wl-right{padding-right:0.2em}


  3. ^ Jeff Miller. "Earliest Uses of Symbols of Set Theory and Logic". jeff560.tripod.com. Retrieved 2016-05-05. Miller quotes Joseph Warren Dauben (1990). Georg Cantor:His Mathematics and Philosophy of the Infinite. ISBN 9780691024479. : "His new numbers deserved something unique. ... Not wishing to invent a new symbol himself, he chose the aleph, the first letter of the Hebrew alphabet...the aleph could be taken to represent new beginnings..."


  4. ^ Jech, Thomas (2003), Set Theory, Springer Monographs in Mathematics, Berlin, New York: Springer-Verlag


  5. ^ Szudzik, Mattew (31 July 2018). "Continuum Hypothesis". Wolfram Mathworld. Wolfram Web Resources. Retrieved 15 August 2018.


  6. ^ Szudzik, Mattew (31 July 2018). "Continuum Hypothesis". Wolfram Mathworld. Wolfram Web Resources. Retrieved 15 August 2018.


  7. ^ aleph numbers at PlanetMath.org.


  8. ^ Harris, Kenneth (April 6, 2009). "Math 582 Intro to Set Theory, Lecture 31" (PDF). Department of Mathematics, University of Michigan. Retrieved September 1, 2012.




References



  • Sierpiński, Wacław (1958), Cardinal and ordinal numbers., Polska Akademia Nauk Monografie Matematyczne, 34, Warsaw: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe, MR 0095787


External links




  • Hazewinkel, Michiel, ed. (2001) [1994], "Aleph-zero", Encyclopedia of Mathematics, Springer Science+Business Media B.V. / Kluwer Academic Publishers, ISBN 978-1-55608-010-4

  • Weisstein, Eric W. "Aleph-0". MathWorld.




Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Information security

Lambak Kiri

章鱼与海女图